There are innumerable arguments about the legitimacy and morality of government and its proper scope, all of which are worth exploring. Public Choice Theory examines an entirely different question than what government ought to do. It asks what government actually does.
Public Choice is the study of the operations of government using the analytical tools of economics. In short, the same assumptions about human interests and actions are applied to the political market as the market for economic goods.
The real power in this theory is its ability to reveal how poorly government works in practice. It does not address lofty notions of the ideal state, or the right and wrong of state action, but rather examines the actual operations of states to see if they are effective at achieving their stated goals.
Public Choice theory by that name is relatively new among schools of economic thought, but the application of economic insights to political institutions is not new.
This is a basic overview of the core insights of Public Choice Theory.
Why government?
The need for government is typically justified by the claim that there are certain “public goods” which cannot be supplied by the voluntary forces of the market, but are nonetheless beneficial to all members of society.
The standard analysis describes goods like roads, for example, and spends a great deal of time analyzing the incentives in the market to explain why roads will not be sufficiently provided. It is supposed that everyone would benefit from a road and it would be “non-excludable”. That is, once constructed, it would be too costly to prevent members of society from using the road whether they paid for it or not. Because of this non-excludability, rationally self-interested individuals would be unwilling to contribute to a voluntary fund for the maintenance of the road. Each individual knows that their contribution is small relative to the entire road fund, and furthermore that without their contribution, they will still enjoy use of the road. With these incentives facing everyone, no one will contribute and the road will decay. It is in no one’s individual interest to pay for road maintenance, but everyone would be better off if each person contributed.
You may substitute any number of “public goods” for roads, but the standard analysis is the same. It looks closely at the incentives in the market, deems them unfit to provide the good in question, and concludes that the good must be provided by the state.
Let’s grant, for the sake of argument, that the analysis of the market is correct. (There is ample evidence to the contrary of course: Nearly any “public good” you can imagine has at some point been, or is even today, provided by the private sector, even though theorists sometimes fail to imagine how.) If we accept the inability of the market to sufficiently provide the good, there’s still something missing in the standard story.
All the time is spent analyzing what would happen in a market of rationally self-interested individuals and what the incentive structure would produce. When deemed insufficient, no time is spent analyzing what happens when government attempts to provide the good. (This is what Art Carden has colorfully dubbed the political economy of the Underpants Gnomes.) What happens if we use the same assumptions and analytical rigor when examining government provision of public goods as we do for the market?
Political self-interest
In order for government to solve public goods problems it would require selfless politicians. The political actors who use tax dollars to maintain the road would have to be counted on to discharge this duty rather than, say, spend the money on something else or give it to a subpar contractor who happens to be their friend. But if we are consistent in our analysis, we must treat politicians as rationally self-interested people too. They have every incentive to act to their own benefit at the expense of the taxpayer.
How can the self-interest of the political class be kept in check? The textbook answer is democracy.
Democracy as a restraint
Does democracy ensure that the political class will pursue the interest of the public, rather than their own? The answer is a resounding ‘no’. The reason is because voters are also self-interested.
It is well known that, statistically, an individual vote in a state or national election is meaningless. The odds of one vote changing the outcome of a national election are worse than the odds of winning the lottery. The odds of getting in a car accident on the way to the polls are greater than the odds of an individual vote making a difference. In other words, the possibility of an individual vote resulting in measurable benefits to that individual is almost nonexistent.
In order for democracy to keep the self-interest of politicians in check, voters need to have an understanding of what they’re voting on and what policies are good for the whole of society. This would take a tremendous amount of time and effort. A single bill may be several hundred pages of technical legalese, and most elected officials vote on hundreds of bills in each term. For a citizen to be informed enough to know what policies are good for society vs. good only for the politicians is incredibly costly. Yet the individual vote of a citizen has almost no chance of changing the outcome or conferring any benefit. The rational response is to be ignorant of policies, because the cost of being informed is so much greater than the chance of benefiting from being informed. A dedicated, informed voter has one vote that is cancelled out by just one ignorant voter.
The result is what economists call “rational ignorance”. Voters are ignorant of policies and positions because to be otherwise is a burden with no reward. But there are some people for whom knowledge of policies is beneficial; namely, the small groups that are directly affected by those policies.
A bill to give a $100 million subsidy to Acme co. is worth a great deal to that company. They would not be foolish to spend $99 million lobbying for its passage, as they would still come out $1 million ahead. Voters, on the other hand, have no incentive to lobby against the bill because spread out across taxpayers it might cost each just a few dollars, while active opposition – even just a letter to a Congressperson – might take hours of time that could be spent doing something worth more than a few dollars. This is why democracy results in concentrated benefits and dispersed or diffused costs. The rationale of politics is to provide benefits to concentrated interests and spread the costs as far and wide as possible – including into the future by way of borrowing or inflating to pay for it.
The obvious result is a myriad of special interests seeking benefits at the expense of the broader public. In the end, everyone is worse off, but every group has the incentive to continue to seek privileges, if for no other reason than to offset the costs they are bearing for the privileges lavished on every other group. This is why Frederic Bastiat described the state as, “That great fiction by which everyone tries to live at the expense of everyone else.” It has been described elsewhere as a game where people stand in a circle and the state takes a penny from each person, then awards five pennies to one of them at the end of the round (the other five being kept by the state). The game is repeated until each person has been the “winner” of five pennies at least once. They all begrudge the loss of a single penny each round, but all eagerly expect to be the winner in another round, not realizing that at the end of the game every single person in the circle has less than they started with.
The incentives in a democratic system lead to special interests lobbying for and receiving privileges at the expense of society. Far from keeping the self-interest of politicians in check, instead democracy promotes and rewards it, so long as those politicians also provide benefits to every imaginable minority and hand the majority the bill.
But let’s ignore all that…
Let’s assume away rational ignorance on the part of voters. Let’s pretend that voters will expend every effort to become knowledgeable and constrain the self-interest of politicians. Let’s say the “will of the voters” can keep officials in check.
But what is “the will of the voters”? It is not an easy question to answer. Let’s walk through the selection of a preferred policy through the democratic process. The policy in question is what to do with troops in Iraq.
Option A: Keep troop levels the same
Option B: Increase troop levels
Option C: Remove all troops
Now let’s look at the preferences of three different voters.
Voter 1: A>B>C – Prefer to keep the same level of troops, but if any change is going to occur would rather increase troops and “get the job done” than to pull out.
Voter 2: B>C>A – Prefer to increase troops to “get the job done”, but if that’s not going to happen better to pull out entirely than keep the same level of troops.
Voter 3: C>A>B – Prefer to remove all troops, but short of that, better to leave the same number of troops there than to add more.
Whether or not you agree with the preferences of these voters, it is clear that each of them has a rational sequence of preferences among the given policy options. You probably have met people who hold each of these views. To determine the “will of the voters”, let’s put these options to a vote and see what policy the elected officials should follow…
In a vote between policy A and B, policy A would win. Two of the voters prefer A to B. If we put policy B and C to a vote, policy B would win. Finally, if we put policy A and C to a vote, policy C would win.
So what is the will of the voters? According to the votes, they prefer A>B, B>C, and C>A. In practical terms, it means the “will of the voters” is to have the same level of troops instead of more, more troops instead of none, and no troops instead of the same number. That would be like a person saying that, between Snickers, Baby Ruth and Heath bars, they prefer Snickers above all, followed by Baby Ruth, followed by Heath, which they prefer to Snickers. This is a non-transitive set of preferences, and is one of the definitions of a mentally impaired person. The will of the voters is a logical impossibility. This is called vote cycling, or Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem.
You can see how, based on the structure of the voting process, entirely different preferences can emerge. This means that even if the voters were well informed, democracy would fail to provide a clear “will of the voters” for politicians to be accountable to. Take this simple example of three clear policies and substitute a number of politicians each with positions on dozens of different policies and it is utterly impossible to know what the “will of the voters” is based on the results of elections.
Okay, let’s also ignore all that…
Let’s go a step further. Let’s pretend that voters are not only informed, but that by some magic the “will of the voters” is clear as day and easily ascertainable through the democratic process. If we grant these two monumental assumptions surely democracy will serve to protect the interest of the public at large from those of politicians and special interests…right? Unfortunately for democracy, its problems are even greater than rational ignorance and the impossibility of a clear “will of the voters.” The “will of the voters” may actually be for policies that are harmful to those voters themselves and the public at large. This is what Brian Caplan has called “Rational irrationality”.
Voting is not the same as purchasing something in the market. To vote is to express a preference, while to purchase something is to demonstrate a preference. Voting, like filling out an anonymous survey, is “free”. You can voice whatever preference you like without being held accountable for the result. Imagine if a grocery store sent a survey to nearby residents and asked them to vote for what items they would like on the shelves. It’s not hard to see what a disaster this would be for patrons of the store. People may vote for bizarre items just to be funny. People may vote for items they think they ought to buy, rather than items they actually do buy; or items they think their neighbors should like, rather than what they do like.
When people are asked whether they like it when companies outsource production to countries where labor is cheaper, most will say no. Yet many of these same people purchase lower priced items produced overseas instead of more expensive domestically produced alternatives. Their stated preference is for American made goods, but they demonstrate by their actions that they see foreign goods as more beneficial to their own well-being. It is “free” to say you want to protect American manufacturing jobs, and it may feel better to voice that opinion, but if faced with the costs that result from the outcome of a protective tariff, people may choose otherwise.
Voting is a free way to indulge irrational biases. Voters do not vote for policies that they themselves favor, but for policies that make them feel good to vote for. They vote for the candidate who promises to stop immigration because it feels right on an emotional level, yet they hire the migrant worker to landscape their business because it benefits them more than the alternative.
Voting separates the voter from the results of his vote, and creates an incentive to use votes carelessly and in ways contrary to his actual interest. Even if we grant the most generous assumptions imaginable – voters who are fully informed no matter the cost to them and the fact that they have no chance of benefiting from being informed, and a democratic process that can clearly express a single “will of the voters” across a complex range of issues – democracy still provides incentives for policies that harm the public by their own definition.
Public goods revisited
We began the exploration of how government works by assuming it was the solution to public goods problems. Government was supposed to the solve those instances where it is in no individual’s interest to bear the cost of overcoming a problem, but where everyone would be better off if all would share the cost. What Public Choice reveals is that, rather than solving public goods problems, democracy is the greatest public good of all. It is in no individual’s interest to bear the cost of being informed and voting their true preferences, but in order for the system to work everyone would have to sacrifice their self-interest to the greater good.
Regardless of the moral standing of the state, the practical outcomes of government activity are inferior to what the market produces. Even in cases of so-called “market failure”, it may be better for the government to take no action than to intervene and make things worse with the even greater “government failure” embedded in the incentives of the state. In other words, whether or not government is an evil, it may be an unnecessary one.
Hope?
To reduce the harmful effects of the perverse incentives in government, it must be reduced to its smallest possible form. The scope of activities taken on by the state must be narrowed as far as can be accomplished. Many practitioners of Public Choice theory advocate constitutional checks, supermajorities and other adjustments to government procedures in the hope that these will change the incentives and create a more accountable government. The flaw in this approach is that the parties responsible for making such changes are themselves part of the government apparatus and face all the same incentives they are hoping to overcome.
If followed to its logical conclusion, pure Public Choice theory would lead us to believe that the state would be all-encompassing even now. The incentives are aligned, for example, so that there should be mandates on every facet of our lives in every industry and the sphere of freedom should be nonexistent. Yet this is not the state of affairs in which we find ourselves. Why, given the incentives in the system, has the state been restrained at all, little though the restraint may seem to us?
In the final analysis, it is the beliefs of the public that create the ultimate check on the state. If the public has a firm belief that alcohol should be legal, the interests of bootleggers and Baptists will not be sufficient to bring prohibition back. We cannot reasonably expect incentives to be overcome or people to act against their self-interest, but we can and do see incentives change as people’s view of what is in their self-interest changes. Most people would not find it worth their while to attempt to stop the passage of a subsidy to Midwestern beet farmers; but a great number of people consider it worth their while to attempt to stop the passage of a new prohibition bill.
Only when it is widely believed that farm subsidies are as absurd as alcohol prohibition will the incentives change enough to produce a more restrained state.
Further reading
Public Choice, A Primer – Eamonn Butler
Beyond Politics – Randy T. Simmons
Government Failure – Gordon Tullock, Arthur Seldon, and Gordon L. Brady
————————————————–
*I am indebted to Professor Benjamin Powell for the basic structure of the arguments in this article, which he presents in a lecture for the Foundation for Economic Education.
*I am indebted to Matthew Mitchell for the example of vote cycling.
*This was originally posted at LibertarianChristians.com. I thought it prudent to repost here because there are so few basic intros to Public Choice and because many would-be readers who are not interested in Christianity or Libertarianism may overlook it at the original site.
Like this:
Like Loading...